p.l.e. logophilosophy.lander.edu                                 Title:  Ethics

Ethics Homepage  > Self-Interest  > Aristotle       

   
 

 

Bust of Aristotle, Marble
	Copy of Lysipppos Greek Bronze
	Museo Nozionale Romano Di Palazzo Altemps
	Rome, Italy
	Public Domain

Philosophy 302: Ethics
Aristotle's Ethics


Abstract: Aristotle's ethics is a common sense ethics built on naturalism and self-realization. Of all the classical ethical theories considered here, his is the farthest from an ethics of self-interest.


I. With respect to the good, right, and happiness, the good for Aristotle is not a disposition to act in a certain way. The good involves a teleological system where living well and doing well are the highest end of life: goods such as strength, wealth, and friendships facilitate a well-lived life.

 

A. For Aristotle the (highest) good is that to which all things aim. Something is good if it performs its proper function. E.g., a good coffee cup is good if it is made of good materials, is of the right size and shape, retains heat, and is convenient in use, and so forth. A good red oak tree is well shaped, is healthy, has good soil and light, and so on.

 

 

1. A right action is that which is conducive to the good, and different goods correspond to the differing sciences and arts.

 

 

2. "The good" or best good is that which is desired for its own sake and for the sake which we desire all other ends or goods. E.g. we desire friends not as something good in itself but as something to help facilitate eudaemonia.

For human beings, eudaemonia is activity of the soul in accordance with arete (excellence, virtue, or "what we are good for"). Descriptively, eudaemonia is living well and doing well in the affairs of the world.


 

B. The good of human beings cannot be answered with the exactitude of a mathematical problem since mathematics starts with general principles and argues to conclusions.

 

 

1. Ethics starts with our actual moral judgments prior to our ability to formulate of general principles.

 

 

2. Aristotle presupposes people have a natural tendency to seek what they think is good or beneficial.

 

C. Aristotle distinguishes between happiness (eudaemonia) and moral virtue:

 

 

1. Moral virtue is not the end of life, for some morally virtuous persons are inactive, miserable and unhappy.

 

 

2. Happiness, the end of life and that to which all persons aim, is activity in accordance with reason.

The arete or peculiar excellence of persons is reason.


 

 

 

a. Happiness is an activity involving both moral and intellectual arete.

 

 

 

b. Some external goods, such as friendship, sufficient wealth, and sufficient influence, are necessary in order to exercise that activity.

II. The Good Character.

 

A. People have a natural capacity for good character, and it is developed through practice. The capacity does not come first — it's developed through practice.



1. The sequence of character development in human behavior raises the question of which is preeminent — acts or dispositions. Their interaction is elucidated by Aristotle's distinction between acts which create good dispositions and acts which flow from the good disposition once good character has been created.
2. Arete is a disposition developed out of a capacity by the proper exercise of that capacity.

 

 

3. Habits are developed through acting; a person's character is the structure of habits formed by what we do.

 

B. Virtue, arete, or excellence is defined as a mean between two extremes of excess and defect with respect to a feeling or action as the practically wise person would determine it. This mean cannot be calculated a priori.

 

 

1. The mean is relative to the individual and the individual's circumstances. For example, consider the following traits:

 

 

 

Defect

Mean

Excess

 

 

 

 

 

 

cowardliness

courage

rashness

 

 

 

 

 

 

humility

pride

vanity

 

 

 

 

 

 

frugal

giving

 liberal

 

 

 

 

 


2. The level of courage necessary is different for a philosophy student, a commando, and a systems programmer.

 

 

3. Phronesis or practical wisdom is the ability to see the right thing to do in the circumstances. Notice, especially here, Aristotle's theory does not imply ethical relativism because of the appropriate standards human action in accordance with the appropriate mean for that person in that situation.

 

 

4. In the ontological dimension of virtue as a factual instance, virtue is a mean; in the axiological dimension of virtue as a value, it is an extreme or an excellence.

E.g., Martin Luther King, Jr. relates his realization of this difference in his “Letter from Birmingham Jail” when he wrote: “Dr. Martin Luther King”
			Birmingham Alabama Police Dept. 
			Photo Mugshot April 12, 1963
			Public Domain

“You speak of our activity in Birmingham as extreme … But though I was initially disappointed at being categorized as an extremist, as I continued to think about the matter I gradually gained a measure of satisfaction from the label. Was not Jesus an extremist for love … Was not Amos an extremist for justice … Was not Paul an extremist for the Christian gospel … Perhaps the South, the nation and the world are in dire need of creative extremists.” [United States. Congress. House. Committee on the Judiciary. Subcommittee on Crime. Application of the RICO Law to Nonviolent Advocacy Groups: Hearing Before the Subcommittee On Crime of the Committee On the Judiciary, House of Representatives, One Hundred Fifth Congress, Second Session, July 17, 1998. (Washington: U.S. G.P.O., 2000), 81.]

 

 

5.Some presumptively virtuous behaviors can be an extreme as when, for example, the medieval philosopher Peter Abélard explains:

“No long time thereafter I was smitten with a grievous illness, brought upon me by my immoderate zeal for study.” [Peter Abélard, Historia Calamitatum trans. Ralph Adams Cram (St. Paul, MN: Thomas A. Boyd, 1922), 4.]

 

 

6. Hartmann's Diagram:

The diagram illustrates virtue considered in its ontological dimension as a mean and virtue in the axiological dimension as an extreme or an excellence. [Nicolai Hartmann, Ethik (Berlin: W. de Gruyter, 1926), 401.]
 

 

 

7. Pleasure and pain are powerful determinants of our actions.

III. Pleasure is the natural accompaniment of unimpeded activity. Pleasure, as such, is neither good nor bad.

 

A. Even so, pleasure is something positive when its effect is to perfect the exercise of activity. Everything from playing chess to making love is improved with skill.

 

B. Pleasure cannot be directly sought — it is the side-product of activity. Pleasure is only one element in the development of happiness.

 

C. The good person, the one who has attained eudaemonia, is the standard by which pleasant or unpleasant is known. (For more on Aristotle's view of pleasure, see Aristotle on Pleasure on this website.)

IV. Friendship: a person's relationship to a friend is the same as the relation to oneself, according to Aristotle. A good friend is thought of as a second self.

 

A. In friendship a person loves himself not as someone seeking wealth for himself, but as someone who gives his money away to receive honor.

 

B. Aristotle distinguishes three kinds of friendship:

 

 

1. Utility: friendships of worthwhile mutual benefit in accomplishment

 

 

2. Pleasure: friendships of contentment, gratification, and mutual while having a good time together.

 

 

3. The Good: friendships of virtue and character who flourish together — a friendship which endures as long as both retain their character.

V. The Contemplative Faculty — the exercise of perfect happiness in intellectual or philosophic activity.

 

A. Reason is the highest faculty of human beings. We can engage in it longer than other activities.

 

B. Contemplation is the highest part of our self and form of activity. Philosophy is loved as an end-in-itself, and consequently Aristotle implies the realization of eudaemonia (or happiness) requires leisure and self-sufficiency as an environment for contemplation.


Recommended Sources

Quiz on Aristotle's Ethics:  Aristotle's ethical theory reviewed in true/false questions.
Quiz on the Doctrine of the Mean:
A short quiz on Aristotle's Doctrine of the Mean from Introduction to Philosophy.
Aristotle's Ethics: An excellent discussion from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy of Aristotle's ethics drawn from the Nicomachean Ethics and the Eudemian Ethics by Richard Kraut.

Ethics Homepage     

 
Socrates and Plato   Top of Page   Aristotle and Pleasure

Send corrections or suggestions to webmaster@philosophy.lander.edu
Read the disclaimer concerning this page.
2001-2014 GFDL



Problems  |  Egoistic Theories  |  The Good  |  Duty Ethics  |  Utilitarianism  |  Rights  |

.