Cite Entry
October 9 2025
06:55 EDT
Class Debate,
Carcilse Indian School,
1879-1918
Library of Congress
LC-USZ62-47083
|
Introduction to Philosophy
The Principle of Charity
Abstract: The principle of charity in much of philosophy and the
sciences is a presumption whereby preconceptions about an argument, a topic, or a theory are set
aside in the attempt to seek an understanding of its most cogent exposition. In other fields
of study, the formulation of the principle of charity is often contextually subject-dependent.
- The Principle of Charity in many areas of
the interpretation of discourse is a methodological presumption made in seeking to understand a
point of view whereby we seek to understand that view in its best and most cogent form before
subjecting the view to evaluation. Often the principle is a means of resolving misunderstanding
a speaker's or writer's meaning or ideas while engaged in rational inquiry.
- The principle of charity is meant to be an integral aspect of interpreting a belief system,
point of view, or a standpoint rather than meant as an imposed heuristic principle of rational
reconstruction of an opponent's position. (Many criticisms of the traditional principle of charity
overlook this prerequisite.) The primary purpose of such a discussion is to seek the the most
consistent and true standpoint.
- While suspending our own beliefs, we seek a sympathetic understanding of the ideas
presented.
- We assume for the moment the ideas are credible even though our initial reaction might
be to disagree; we seek to tolerate ambiguity for the larger aim of understanding ideas
which might prove useful and helpful.
- Emphasis is placed on seeking to understand rather than on seeking contradictions or
difficulties.
- Care need be taken to assure key terms are clearly and accurately defined and agreed
upon.
- We seek to understand the ideas in their most convincing form and actively attempt to
resolve contradictions. If more than one view is presented, we choose the one that appears
the most cogent. However, where possible, the resultant interpretation of the standpoint under
investigation must be acknowledged by the speaker as an accurate, fair, and clear
re-statement prior to attempted resolution of the issues.
- The normative use of the principle is meant to apply to discourse where there is a genuine
attempt to reach an understanding — and not to persuasive discourse or contests to win an
argument or defeat an opponent.
- In rhetoric, debate, and persuasion, the use of the principle of charity for
accurate, fair, and just resolution of differences by reducing the chances of misrepresenting a
point of view or committing straw man fallacy has
been criticized on the grounds that seeking the most cogent exposition of an opponent's
standpoint will likely misconstrue the opposing position.
- In popular culture the practice of interpreting the most rational and coherent version of
an opponents position is often termed a “steel man” interpretation (as opposed to
the straw man fallacy which occurs when an adversary's position is misrepresented and then
rejected as if it were the argument at issue).
- One common criticism of the use of the principle of charity is the charge that in being
“charitable” the initial standpoint or point of view has been misrepresented
because the standpoint's meaning or stated belief has been altered in the re-statement.
A related criticism is that the “so called” more rational and cogent
“charitable” position is likely to be a case of confirmation bias. The
interpreter can be seen as intentionally or unintentionally “misconstruing”
the initial standpoint to fit the interpreter's own
predispositions.
So, what appears to be rational to the interpreter may not seen as rational to the
original speaker. Disagreements like these arise because not everyone shares the same
understanding of true belief and legitimate rationality.
- These criticisms are sometimes countered by recognizing that the central purpose of
rhetorical, forensic, or persuasive discourse is not intended to be truth-seeking
— their intent is to alter attitudes and beliefs. That is, the purpose of rhetoric
and persuasion is not to find, evaluate, and understand what is true. In the persuasive
arts, rhetoric, as the language art of persuasive speaking or writing, is used not for
understanding but for the specific purpose of changing attitudes and beliefs.
It's important to recognize that the use of the principle of charity in philosophical
discourse was never specifically intended to reach
consensus, but to achieve knowledge and
understanding. Just as a philosopher is unlikely to be in a position to understand algebraic
geometry, so also an irrational person is unlikely to understand what makes a good
argument.
So, in many fields of controversy, the assumption of something like “equal standing”
among disputants might not hold since the disputants might not share a common background of
knowledge, a common understanding of rationality, or a belief that inherent bias can be
surmounted through open inquiry. Nevertheless, the question of the necessity of “equal
standing” for reaching agreement on controversial issues would be an exceedingly difficult
precondition to impose for contentious disputes.
- The principle of charity, in general, is a methodological principle —
ideas can be critiqued after achieving an adequate understanding of the author's intent
and standpoint. It's important to point out that the original presumption of setting aside our
own beliefs and assuming the standpoint at issue is a substantive and provisional step taken
prior to evaluation of the point of view under consideration.
- Hence, we should initially listen or read new material as if we had no
preconceptions about the subject. We seek to be open and receptive.
- This attitude, if maintained, frees the conditioned mind and enables it to absorb and
understand the unfamiliar text.
- In essence, we just start with a simple desire to grasp any points which might not be
understood upon first acquaintance.
- The method is used in the preparation of a transitional understanding for further inquiry
and resolution of the text after a preliminary foundation of agreement.
- Refinements of the principle of charity in philosophy include the principle of rational
accommodation whereby we attempt to maximize truth and the principle of humanity
where we attempt to maximize intelligibility.
- Willard Van Orman Quine's version of the principle (in the context of understanding a
different language) is this maxim of translation: “[A]ssertions startlingly false on the
face of them are likely to turn on hidden differences of languages.” The view under examination
is necessarily to be assumed to be mostly true.
What this means in practice is our own language shapes to some extent the interpretation since
translation can only be done within the limits of our own language.
- Donald Davidson suggests the principle of charity (or, in his words, “the
principle of rational accommodation”) should attempt to “maximize” sense
and “optimize” agreement when invoked with respect to coherence and factual
correspondence of what is said. We should seek a coherent understanding supported by a
common base of understanding.
- The principle of coherence seeks “logical consistency in the thought of
the speaker.” The interpreter is
to translate the speaker's discourse so as to accentuate the logical agreement of the speaker's
statements with what the interpreter takes the speaker's beliefs to be — not
what the interpreter's own beliefs are. The principle of charity recognizes that there is no
independent objective viewpoint from which to judge the speakers discourse. Eventually, any
objectivity is framed from intersubjectivity of speaker and interpreter.
- The principle of correspondence seeks “the same features of the world that
[we] would be responding to under similar
circumstances.” In practice, this
principle can only be an ideal since different states of affairs ofen mean different things to
different people when they are experienced from different viewpoints. (E.g., the British
tend to be slightly amused at U.S.'s July 4th holiday (U.S.'s 1776 historical independence day),
whereas Americans, for the most part, have no awareness of Britian's Guy Fawkes Day which
commemorates the failed 1605 Gunpowder Plot.)
- Consequently, Davidson's account more or less presupposes a truth-functional theory of
meaning of a system of truth-value statements.
- The humanity principle as put forward by Richard Grandy is that we should
initially interpret a different philosophical point of view in accordance with the assumption
that the interrelation of belief and reality being expressed is similar to our
own. In a similar manner, Donald Dennett
explains the principle of humanity, “[O]ne should attribute to [the person's whose view
we are attempting to understand] … the propositional attitudes one supposes one would
have oneself in those circumstances.”
The principle of humanity is intended to perform the same role as the principle of charity.
In many subject areas other than traditional Western thought, the principle of rational
accommodation cannot emphasized. Interpretation or translation is context-dependent. In numerous
instances of the thought of different cultures including our own, discourse with respect to paradigm
change in the sciences, in some domains of Continental philosophy, in poetry and literature, in
aesthetics, and in religion, sometimes fidelity of content, imagination, or even empathy is prized over
consistency, correspondence and familiar attitudes.
In the following examples, the principle of charity with its features of rational accommodation
and the humanity principle seems to be inapplicable to an open-minded interpretation of the ideas
in the discourse presented:
- In fundamental physics, Feynman writes in his Nobel Prize Lecture about struggling with
the notion of backward causation in quantum electrodynamics:
“[A]ll physicists know from studying Einstein and Bohr, that sometimes an idea
which looks completely paradoxical at first, if analyzed to completion in all detail and
in experimental situations, may, in fact, not be
paradoxical.”
The topic of retrocausality as well as that of quantum entanglement leads to paradox in
rational-thought experiments. The consequences for “rationally accommodating” these
proposed phenomena are contrary to our intuitive understanding of the world. So Feynman
suspends presumption of the arrow of time and pursues the theoretical consequences as if
that belief were the case.
- In literature, Dostoevsky writes in his Notes from Underground that
what is not in one's own interest may be precisely that which is in one's own interest:
“Who was it first said, first propounded the theory, that man does evil
only because he is blind to his own interests, but that if he were enlightened, if his
eyes were opened to his real, his normal interests, he would at once cease to do evil
and become virtuous and noble … since when, during these thousands of years, has
man ever acted solely in accordance with his own interests? … What if human
advantage not only may, but does, consist of the fact that, on certain occasions, man
may desire, not what is good for him, but what is
bad?”
Through consideration of the seemingly contradictory idea that one's advantage can be what
might not be in one's actual advantage, Dostoevsky reveals the notion of unconscious motivation.
- In Hinduism, God may be worshiped as a child when the devotee worships Krishna. A
Christian, uncharitably, might be inclined to think Hinduism strange since the baby Krishna is
loved as an advocates' own child. Yet, for the Christian, the notion of the Christ Child could
be suggested by the application of the principle of humanity in order to help understand this
Hindu ideal. Swami Vivekanda writes:
“The next [human representation of the ideal of divine love] is what is known as
Vâtsalya, loving God not as our Father but as our Child. This may look peculiar,
but it is a discipline to enable us to detach all ideas of power from the concept of God.
… [T]he Christian and the Hindu can realize [this idea of God as Child] easily,
because they have the baby Jesus and the baby Krishna.”
The similarity of attitude and belief between Christians and Hindus in this regard helps
remove difficulty in understanding by persons who share this similar pattern of thought, but
may pose a problem for everyday rational understanding by others.
- In this example from poetry, literary critic [Compton?] Mackenzie is quoted as
pointing out that when Percy Bysshe Shelley wrote the poem “To a Skylark” …:
“Hail to the blithe spirit,
Bird thou never wert,”
…he wasn't asserting the bird did not exist
— yet that would be literally what Shelly wrote. Instead, a charitable interpretation would
be that Shelly is metaphorically describing the “blithe spirit” as a transcendent
quality of delight and song — not an earthly bird of a particular biological species.
English critic R.L. Mégroz noted a century ago, “[T]he dictum attributed to
Longinus, ‘Beautiful words are the very and peculiar light of the mind,’ can only
be understood when some other than their lexical sense is attached to
them.”
- Art critic J. Nilsen Laurvik explains French impressionist painter Paul Cézanne's
art as exhibiting “unflinching, literal-minded adherence to facts” and as
“mathematically precise and hence rigorously truthful”:
“[H]is final emphasis [was] on the sub-structure of form. To him a sphere was not always
round, a cube always square or an ellipse always elliptical. … [I]f we could dissociate
the sense of roundness from the appearance of roundness as did Cézanne,
we would find large surfaces of spheroids quit flat. Therein lies the real secret of the art of
Cézanne who is the first of realists.”
So, here, in art as well, fidelity of interpretation, and perhaps some sense of empathy for
Laurvik's meaning, is to be prioritized over accommodation of rational coherence, empirical
correspondence, and similarity of experience.
Notes
[Most links go to page cited]
“[I]n the collective representations of primitive mentality, objects, beings, phenomena can
be … in a way incomprehensible to us … [T]he opposition between the one and the many, the
same and another, and so forth, does not impose upon this mentality the necessity of affirming one
of the terms if the other be denied, or vice versa. … [T]he Trumai (a tribe of Northern Brazil)
say that they are aquatic animals.—The Bororo (a neighbouring tribe) boast that they are red
araras (parakeets).”
[How Natives
Think trans. Lilian A. Clare (New York: Knopf, 1925), 77.]
Accurate interpretation need reflect such “incomprehensibilities” even though many
texts like this one violate both the principles of coherence and correspondence required by the
principle of charity. As well, if we follow Davidson's requirement that most any interpreted
account is to be considered true, how could psychoanalytical interpretations of the experiences of
schizophrenics with prominent paranoid symptoms be charitably be interpreted? [Q.v., Mathieu
Frérejouan, “The Myth of Irrationality: A Wittgensteinian Approach to Delusions and to the
Principle of Charity,” in (In)coherence is Discourse: Formal and Conceptual Issues of
Language, eds. M. Amblard, M. Musiol and M. Rebuschi (Cham, CH: Springer Nature, 2021), 138.]
D..T. Correia and C. Siopa argue that the interpretation of the reports of delusional people, although
in most respects irrational, can be interpreted in a similar manner as we interpret our dreams: neither
delusions nor dreams are rational, but both experiences have meaning:
“We believe the patient knows herself to be Christ, yet simultaneously that we
cannot know her to be so. And this is a characterization of delusion that may be shared both by
patient and therapist; it provides a foothold for agreement rather than antagonism.”
[Rick Bellaar and Jasper Feyaerts,
“Meaning
and Delusion” in The Philosophy and Psychology of Delusions: Historical and Contemporary
Perspectives eds. A. Falcato and J Gonçalves (New York: Routledge, 2024), 101.]
Just as we can know our conscious life and our dreams so likewise a delusional person can know
conscious life and delusions without imposing the same rational standard on both. Many situations exist
where we do not share the same rational and empirical norms, nor even the same
attitudes as expressed in the discourse presented.↩
Further Reading:
- “Principle of Charity.”
Philosophical and rhetorical principles are briefly summarized by Wikipedia.
Charitable interpretation is described as an interpretation in the strongest possible manner
while maximizing rationality.
- “Charity
Principles in Philosophical Argumentation,” a paper by R.A.J. Shields, argues that
the principle is pragmatic, not just moral or epistemic. He describes and organizes some of
the better known forms of the principle of charity. [39 (2025) Argumentation,
83-102.]
- “Rationality and
Charity,” a classic paper by P. Thagard and R.E. Nisbett discusses some of the
differing degrees of rigor in foundational interpretations of charity and concludes that
there are often empirically justifiable reasons for interpreting arguments to be irrational.
They propose a more moderate interpretation of the principle when proposers violate normative
standards. [50 (1983) Philosophy of Science, 250-267.]
- “The Principle of Charity in Philosophy” is
discussion on this website of various versions of the principle with examples drawn from various
fields of study. The presentation there emphasizes that the principle is a somewhat idealized
guide with different purposes in different types of deliberation.
“… the principle of charity. This policy calls on us to fit our own propositions
(or our own sentences) to the other person's words and attitudes in such a way as to render
their speech and other behavior intelligible. This necessarily requires us to see others as
much like ourselves in point of overall coherence and correctness — that we see them as
more or less rational creatures mentally inhabiting a world much like our own.”
Donald Davidson, Problems of Rationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 35.
Relay corrections or suggestions to philhelp@gmail
Read the disclaimer concerning this page.
1997-2025 Licensed under GFDL
and Creative
Commons 3.0
The “Copyleft” copyright assures the user the freedom to use,
copy, redistribute, make modifications with the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.
The “Creative Commons” copyright assures the user the freedom
to copy, distribute, display, and modify on the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.
|