Return to Philosophy Web Homepagephilosophy.lander.edu      

Homepage > Logic > Ordinary Language > Reducing Terms         

   
 

Logic Homepage

 

Quizzes
Tests
FAQ
Links
Search
Readings
Archives
Syllabus

 

 

"Camp Life," detail from NOAA Oholo Library, theb2660.Philosophy 103: Introduction to Logic
Reducing the Number of Terms


Abstract: Translation techniques, including immediate inferences, are discussed and used for syllogistic inference.

  1. Arguments in ordinary language need to be translated into standard-form categorical syllogisms before they can be tested. Standard-form translations often require a number of special techniques.

    1. First, the argument must be set up in standard form.

      1. The first sub-step is to find the conclusion.

        1. Use the techniques outlined in the tutorial notes on diagramming arguments. The conclusion can occur anywhere in a passage, although most often it is the last or first sentence. The conclusion is often the "topic" sentence of the paragraph.

        2. If you can not easily determine the conclusion from the use of common premiss and conclusion indicator words, then the conclusion can be found to answer the question you ask of the passage: "What's the point"? or "What are you (i.e., the author of the passage) trying to prove?"

      2. The second sub-step is to reduce the classes to three in number, and place the major premiss first and the minor premiss second so that the argument is transformed into standard order. (Most ordinary language syllogisms do not have all of the same terms of the syllogism expressed in exactly the same words.)

      3. Finally, before testing, each proposition in the argument  is translated in standard-form and order.

    2. Second, the argument is tested for validity by means of Venn Diagrams and the Syllogistic Fallacies.

  2. When the terms of a syllogism do not match exactly, resist the tendency to proclaim  the fallacy of four terms. It may well be that by translating to a synonym or suitable paraphrase, the syllogism can be transformed into a valid argument. Let us consider two ways the reduction of terms can be accomplished..

    1. If the same term is not expressed in exactly the same words, then we translate one of them to match the other so that only three classes in toto are used.

    2. When complementary classes are present in the original argument, often we can reduce the number of terms by using obversion or, less often, contraposition.

  3. Consider the following example illustrating the use of both techniques:

    1. "Not all Americans are religious people, but some are invariable fond of the out doors. It is not surprising, therefore, only some nonreligious people are nature lovers."

    2. To analyze this syllogism, we can begin by identifying the conclusion, which, in turn, enables us to identify the major and minor premisses. The stepwise process is subject to some common procedures.

      Major Premiss: Some Americans are religious people and some Americans are not religious people.

      Minor Premiss: Some Americans are people invariably fond of outdoors.

      Conclusion: Some nature lovers are nonreligious people. (The result from the given exclusive proposition).

    3. Since the major premiss is a compound statement, a syllogism corresponding to each premiss is constructed. If either syllogism proves to be valid, the original argument is said to be valid.

      1. The first argument is ...

        Some Americans are religious people.
        Some Americans are people invariably fond of outdoors.
        _______________________________________
        Some nature lovers are nonreligious people.

        The classes "nature lovers" and "people invariably fond of outdoors" can be considered paraphrases, so we can collapse the minor term to one or the other.

        We can match our major terms by obverting the conclusion to yield the following:

        Some AmericansU are religious peopleU.
        Some AmericansU are nature lovers.
        _______________________________________
        Some nature lovers are not religious peopleD.

        Hence, this argument is shown to be invalid by illicit major as well as fallacy of the undistributed middle.

      2. We now can try the second argument...

        Some Americans are not religious people.
        Some Americans are people invariably fond of outdoors.
        ________________________________________
        Some nature lovers are nonreligious people.

        Once again, the classes "nature lovers" and "people invariably fond of outdoors" can be considered paraphrases, so we can collapse the minor term to nature lovers."

        We can match our major terms by obverting the conclusion to yield the following:

        Some AmericansU are not religious people.
        Some AmericansU are nature lovers.
        __________________________________________
        Some nature lovers are not religious people.

        Hence, this argument is shown to be invalid as well by the fallacy of the undistributed middle term.

      3. Since neither syllogism is valid, the original argument is invalid.

 Return to Logic Homepage


 
Index to Ordinary Language Syllogisms  Top of Page  Translation into Standard Form

Send corrections or suggestions to webmaster@philosophy.lander.edu
Read the disclaimer concerning this page.
11.29.04       © 2004 Licensed under GFDL


Arguments | LanguageFallacies  | Propositions  | Syllogisms  | Translation  | Symbolic

.