Syllogistic Fallacy 2:
The Fallacy of the Undistributed Middle
Term
Abstract: The syllogistic Fallacy of the Undistributed
Middle Term is explained and illustrated with examples.
Fallacy of the undistributed middle term is a
formal fallacy committed in standard form syllogisms whenever
the term appearing in both premises is undistributed.
(I.e., each of middle terms refers to some but not all of
the individuals in the premise statements.)
Example of a distributed and undistributed
term: In the statement …
All [persons]D are [primates].U
…the subject term “persons” is said to be a
distributed term since it refers to, or denotes, each and every
person.
The predicate term “primates” is said to be
undistributed since it does not refer to each and every primate
— “primates” in that sentence only makes
reference to those individuals who are “persons” and
not to other kinds of individuals such as as lemurs or gorillas.
[If you want to review the topic of the distribution of subject
and predicate terms in categorical statements, here's the
link: Distribution of a
Term.]
Example of the Fallacy of an Undistributed Middle Term:
In the following argument, the only persons likely to approve of the
reasoning are those who are focusing only on the truth of the premises and
not the structure of the argument:
All [modern feminists]D are [social equality seekers].U All [protofeminists]D are [social equality seekers].U
All [protofeminists]D are [modern feminists].U
The Venn Diagram is sketched like this:
The blank space in the class of “protofeminists” which is
outside of the class of “modern feminists” (indicated by the
arrow) represents nothing is known about possible individuals existing in this
area. Consequently, the premises allow for the possibility that some
protofeminists are not in the class of “modern feminists.” Thus,
the conclusion …
“All protofeminists are modern feminists”
… has not been deductively proved.
Intuitively, it is fairly evident that for the conclusion to follow
validly, one would have to falsely presuppose the converse major premise …
“All social equality seekers are modern feminists”
… (not the originally given “All modern feminists are
are social equality seekers”). So if the given major premise were to
be converted in this manner, the subject class “social equality
seekers” would become distributed.
A term is distributed if in the context of the statement it refers
to each and every member of the class it denotes; otherwise, the term is
said to be undistributed.
So, with the major premise converted, the validity of the argument
can be illustrated by visualizing how the new argument nests its terms:
protofeminists ⊳ social equality seekers ⊳
modern feminists[1]
However, we know from the meaning of the terms used, not all social
equality seekers are feminists. So, since this premise if false,
the revised argument, although valid, is not
a sound
A sound argument is a valid argument with true premises. (And,
therefore, of course, the conclusion is necessarily true also.)
argument.
In conclusion, in the original argument given above in the lightly
shaded box, the class “social equality seekers” is undistributed
in both premises since each appears in the predicate of an A
statement. Since the middle term is undistributed in both premises,
the argument commits the undistributed middle fallacy.
The Fallacy of the Undistributed Middle
Term occurs when the middle term is undistributed in both premises.
Corresponding Rule: In a valid standard form categorical
syllogism, the middle term must be distributed in at least one
premise.
Reason: for the two terms of the conclusion to
be connected through the third, as in the mechanism shown here, at
least one term must be related to the whole of the class designated
by the middle term.
Otherwise, the connection might be with different parts of the middle
term, as illustrated in the diagram above, and no connection can be made
from S to P since the middle term could be referring to
nothing in common between the two premises.
John Buridan, a fourteenth century logician, explained the reason for
this rule in this manner:
Since the middle is not distributed in either [premise] it is
possible that its conjunction with the major extreme is true for
one thing and its conjunction with the minor is true for another;
and from this no conjunction of the extremes with one another can
be inferred …[2]
The premises can related to each other only if at least one of the
middle terms is distributed.
In the history of logic, occasionally, an undistributed middle
term has been considered an example of equivocation (fallacia
æquivocationis) presumably because the denotation of the
terms are different since the references of the terms are not necessarily
identical in the context of their use.[3]
Note: Remember for the Fallacy of the Undistributed
Middle Term to occur, the middle term must be undistributed in
both premises, not just one premise.
Optional Exercises: Try these challenging exercises. I
think you'll find the mental mastery obtained from the effort well worthwhile.
Try to picture in your mind the position and resultant distribution
of the middle terms from the following syllogistic mood and figures without
writing them down.
Reminder: The position of the middle term is described by the
figure of the syllogism. The
figures are named “1,” “2,”
“3,” and “4.” They are easily
remembered because they form the shape of a flying brick or very wide
“W”.
Think of the middle four Ms on the corners of the orange square
representing the empty space between figures2 and 3.
(1) Visualize the position of the middle term in the following
syllogistic forms without writing the three statements in
standard form syllogisms.
(2) Then picture in your mind the distribution status of the two
statements by the kind of statements used (i.e., an A,
E, I, or O,).
(3) State whether or not the fallacy of the undistributed
middle term occurs.
At first, picturing in your mind the distribution statuses to determine
the fallacy occurs will be challenging, but working through a
few problems will presently become rewarding.
AAA-2
All P is MU All Sis MU
All S is P
Since both premise predicate classes are undistributed, the fallacy of
undistributed middle term occurs.
EAE-1
No MD is P All S is MU
No SD is P
The E major premise distributes all terms, so the undistributed
middle falllacy does not occur.
(The EAE-1 syllogism is the second most common valid syllogism
found in argumentation.)
AAI-2
All P is MU All S is MU
Some S is P
Since both premise predicate classes are undistributed, the fallacy of
undistributed middle term occurs.
AII-4
All P is MU Some MU is P
Some S is P
The middle term is undistributed in both premises, so the fallacy of the
undistributed middle occurs.
OAO-4
Some P is not MU All MD is S
Some S is not PD
The middle term is distributed in the minor premise so the fallacy of the
undistributed middle does not occur.
(Later we will learn since the P term is undistributed in a premise
but distributed in the conclusion, the fallacy
of the illicit major term occurs since only some Ps are referred
to in the premises but all Ps are referred to in the conclusion.
Reasoning from “some” to “all” is not deductive
reasoning.)
III-1
Some MU is P Some S is MU
Some S is P
The middle term is undistributed in both premises, so the fallacy of the
undistributed middle occurs.
AAA-1
All MD is P All S is MU
All S is P
The middle term is undistributed in both premises, so the fallacy of the
undistributed middle occurs.
The AAA-1 syllogism is the most common occurring valid syllogism used in
deductive argumentation.
OII-3
Some MU is not P Some MU is S
Some S is P
The middle term is undistributed in both premises, so the fallacy of the
undistributed middle occurs.
OIO-2
Some PU is not MD Some S is MU
Some S is not PD
The middle term is distributed in the major premise, so the fallacy of the
undistributed term does not occur.
(Later we will study the fallacy of the illicit major term where the
major term P is undistributed in a premise but distributed in
the conclusion. Again, reasoning from “some” to
“all” is not deductive reasoning.)
EOI-1
No MD is P Some S is not MD
Some S is P
The middle term is distributed in both premises so the fallacy of the
undistributed middle does not occur.
(Later we will learn that all syllogisms with two negative
premises are invalid arguments.)
Evaluate the following two syllogisms stated by Biron, a lord attending the king,
in Shakespeare's Love's Labor Lost:
“Well, ‘set thee down, sorrow!” for so they say
the fool said, and so say I, and I the fool. Well proved, wit. By
the Lord, this love is as mad as Ajax: it kills sheep; it kills
me — I am sheep. Well proved again o’ my side.”[4]
Hint: the arguments can be setup as follows:
Argument 1:
The fool said “Well, set thee down sorrow!” I said “Well, set thee down sorrow!” ∴ I am a fool.
Argument 2:
Sheep are killed by a love as mad as Ajax. I am killed by a love as mad as Ajax. ∴ I am a sheep.
Translate the arguments into standard order and form and test for validity.
Argument 1:
A fool is a person who said “Well … sorrow!”U I am a person who said “Well, … sorrow!”U
I am a fool.
The first argument commits the fallacy of the undistributed middle term.
Argument 2:
Sheep are mammals killed by a love as mad as Ajax.U I am a mammal killed by a love as mad as Ajax.U
I am a sheep.
The second argument commits the fallacy of four
terms since in the major premise “killed” denotes
“caused to die” and in the minor premise denotes “caused
pain.”
Notes
1. To say the revised argument is valid does not imply the revised
argument is sound unless both of the premises presented are known to
be true. This argument would be sound if all “social equality
seekers” were understood to be narrowly classified as
“feminists.”↩
4. Shakespeare, Love's Labor Lost IV iii.4. (In Homer's
Illiad, Ajax lost his senses when he was not awarded
Achilles’ armor by the Acheans, and thinking their sheep and cattle
were Acheans, began killing the sheep and cattle.)↩
The “Copyleft” copyright assures the user the freedom
to use,
copy, redistribute, make modifications with the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.
The “Creative Commons” copyright assures the user the
freedom
to copy, distribute, display, and modify on the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.