|
|
Argumentum ad Misericordiam:
Appeal to Pity or Sympathy with Examples
Abstract: The ad misericordiam fallacy
illicitly appeals to pity or a related emotion such as sympathy, compassion,
or mercy in order to gain the acceptance of an unrelated conclusion. Even so,
not all appeals to pity are fallacious. Here, ad misericordiam
arguments, both fallacious and nonfallacious, are defined; their structure is
shown; and both fallacious and nonfallacious ad misericordia
arguments are evaluated with illustrative examples.
Description of ad Misericordiam Arguments
Argumentum ad Misericordiam (argument
from pity or misery): the fallacy committed when pity or a related emotion such as
sympathy, mercy, or compassion is illicitly appealed to for the sake of getting a
conclusion accepted.
- Hence, the fallacy occurs when assent or dissent to a statement or an
argument is sought on the basis of an irrelevant appeal to pity.
- The fallacy can occur in either of two kinds: (1) the appeal to pity
(or a related emotion) is not germane to the conclusion of the argument, or
(2) the enormity of the impassioned appeal is unwarranted given the context
of the argument.
- Generally speaking, in the first fallacious form of the
ad misericordiam argument, the emotional appeal is intentionally
selected to invoke compassion or sympathy in the party to whom the
argument is addressed, but the emotional appeal does not, in itself,
provide relevant evidence for the truth of the conclusion.
For example, consider the following argument from an editorial arguing
in favor of establishing a path to U.S. citizenship for undocumented
immigrants:
“[Texas Senator Ted] Cruz stated his opposition to giving illegal
immigrants a path to U.S. citizenship. … I could introduce Cruz
to an undocumented immigrant, … [a father who] was afraid to go
out to dinner with his kids on Father's Day lest he get stopped by police
and deported.”
The father's fear of deportation is not, by itself, a cogent reason he
should have a path to citizenship. Instead, the emotion appealed to is a
distraction from evidence which could have been adduced.
- Establishing the fallacious nature of the second form of the
ad misericordiam fallacy is sometimes difficult since
the point at which an appeal to pity becomes unwarranted or excessive can
be open to question.
For example, the 19th century forensic legal psychiatrist Isaac Ray
argued morally insane persons capable of sound reasoning are not legally
responsible for their actions and should be accorded the “dignity
and humanity appropriate” for their condition because their
“notions of right and wrong are obscured” in the same way as
we recognize that “the movements of a new-born infant” are
unintentional actions.
Critics argued his justification for not holding morally insane
but logical persons legally responsible is an ad
misericordiam because Ray's reasoning flouts common sense
- Important: Not all appeals to pity are fallacious arguments —
some appeals are appropriate or relevant because the feelings evoked
are logically relevant to the conclusion.
For example, a recommendation to contribute to an organization like Doctors
Without Borders on the basis that this group responds to medical emergencies
around the world resulting from appalling conflict, disease, and natural
disasters would be a nonfallacious appeal. Such an argument provides a
legitimate reason to help alleviate humanitarian crises. Thus, feelings of
pity or sympathy for unfortunate victims of such disasters are both relevant
and appropriate reasons for assistance.
Additional examples of nonfallacious ad misericordiam arguments
are provided in Section IV below.
- A basic schema for the ad misericordiam fallacy is outlined in
the following informal structure:
Guide to the
ad Misericordiam Fallacy
Person L asserts statement p
or argument A.
L deserves pity because of circumstances
y.
[But circumstances y are irrelevant
to p or A.]
∴ Statement p is claimed true
or argument A is claimed to be good.
- Here's a typical example of this fallacy:
“A candidate for a minor county office in rural Iowa once declared,
‘I have six reasons for your voting for me for the job: Annie, Bobbie,
Charlie, Danny, Esther, and Frankie — my six kids who need financial
support.”
The number of children needing financial support is not a relevant or
appropriate job qualification for someone seeking governmental office.
Examples of Ad Misericordiam Fallacies:
Example 1: In the following passage, pity is sought for a banker who must
sell his stocks in order to be appointed as the Director of the U.S. Office of
Management and Budget:
“The Georgia Banker [Bert Lance] should be excused from conflict-of-interest
divestiture problems, former President Jimmy Carter asserted, because
his promise to sell his stock [in order to serve in government] has
depressed its market value.”
Comment: President Carter states that we should allow the banker to keep
his stock because we should feel sorry for him. Nevertheless, employees of the
executive branch of government are required to sell assets in order to avoid
either a conflict of interest or the appearance of a conflict of interest. That is,
they are not permitted to profit from policies that they might be able to influence
as an governmental employee.
Example 2: In the following argument, sympathetic feelings are sought on
behalf of a U.S. state governor being tried for corruption:
“The jury will begin deliberations tomorrow in the Federal conspiracy
and corruption case against Gov. Marvin Mandel of Maryland … Pleading for
understanding of Mr. Mandel, Arnold M. Weiner, the Governor's lawyer, said:
“After four years of this investigation and two years under indictment,
Marvin Mandel is a ruined man. His public life is finished. Every intimate detail
of his personal life has been exposed. Even his health and his strength are gone.
And nothing you can do can restore it.’”
Comment: The fact that Governor Marvin Mandel's life was made miserable
by years of government investigation is not, itself, a valid reason for feeling
sympathy for his being charged with corruption.
Example 3: David Cameron, Prime Minister of the U.K. from 2010-2016, states
regarding Scottish Independence:
“I think that you've heard a lot of arguments that I would call arguments of
the head, arguments about whether Scotland would be better off, more prosperous,
stronger, safer, inside the United Kingdom or not. … But I think it's
also important we make those arguments of the heart … Because I would
be heartbroken if this family of nations that we've put together, and that we
have done such amazing things together, if this family of nations was torn
apart.”
Comment: The speaker's disappointment if Scotland were to become independent
of the U.K. is not logically related to the question of whether or not Scotland would
be advantaged by independence.
Example 4: A journalist argues that the people who work for the media
should not be criticized since many reporters have families, many have lower pay
than some other professions, and some been killed in the course of their duties:
“The horrible murder of two local journalists in Roanoke, Virginia, has
affected me more than I thought it would. … Perhaps this incident will
cause some to reconsider the universal denunciation of ‘the media.’
Most reporters have families and many work for lower pay than they might receive
in other professions.”
Comment: The writer states that journalists should not be thoughtlessly
denounced because they have families and are not well paid. The approval or disapproval
of the writings of journalists should not depend upon their family status or their
salary level. As well, the substantial distinction between murder and universal
denunciation is conflated — the fallacy of ad misericordiam
occurs.
Example 5: U.S. Senator Carl Levin testifies concerning Apple Inc.'s practice of tax avoidance:
”Many U.S. companies, including Apple, shift intellectual property
rights … to offshore affiliates. … The lost tax revenue feeds a
budget deficit that has reached troubling proportions … Because of those
cuts, children across the country won't get early education from Head Start.
Needy seniors will go without meals. Fighter jets sit idle on tarmacs because our
military lacks the funding to keep pilots trained.”
Comment: Even though this argument seems plausible, the fallacy of
ad misericordiam occurs since Senator Levin argues people suffer
because Apple should pay more taxes to help reduce the federal deficit even though
Apple is following present tax-laws. One might as well argue that since Congress
does not presently address these tax loopholes for various reasons, Congress, itself,
is preventing children from getting early education, needy seniors from obtaining
meals, and so forth.
Example 6: Addressing the dock, Robert Emment declaims after receiving a death sentence for high treason for leading the ill-timed Irish Uprising of 1803:
“I wish that my memory and name may animate those who survive me, while
I look down with complacency on the destruction of that perfidious government,
which upholds its dominion by blasphemy of the Most High, which displays its
power over man as over the beasts of the forest, which sets man upon his brother,
and lifts his hand in the name of God against the throat of his fellow who
believes or doubts a little more than the Government standard — a Government
steeled to barbarity by the cries of the orphans and the tears of the widows
which it has made.”
Comment: In this speech, the excessive emotional appeal with phrases of
incisive emotive significance mark this passage as either
an ad populum or an ad
misericordiam argument concluding that the government is perfidious.
Varieties of Ad Misericordiam Arguments
The ad misericordiam fallacy also occurs when such related
emotions such as sympathy, love, regard, mercy, condolence, and compassion are
appealed to in order to establish a conclusion whose truth or falsity is not
relevant to those emotions.
As seen in fallacy Example 6 above, occasionally, an occurrence of a fallacy can be
correctly analyzed as either the ad populum or the ad
misericordiam fallacy since these fallacies sometimes overlap in their appeal.
Consider the following example:
“In the final moments before Paul Manafort's sentencing Wednesday,
the former Trump campaign chief's lawyers appealed for mercy …
Convictions for tax and bank fraud, illegal lobbying and witness tampering
have been ‘very hard’ on his client, Kevin Downing pleaded in
U.S. District Court in Washington on Wednesday. ‘The media attention,
the political motivation … is so unreal.’ U.S. District Judge
Amy Berman Jackson cut him off. ‘Whose political motivation?’
she asked. ‘Everybody out there,’ he said.”
Manafort's lawyers are requesting mercy in the sentencing because they claim
“everybody” has rebuked and has political motives against their
client who just happened to break a few laws. So sympathy is sought for very
hard effects brought about by “everybody's” attention and for
political motivations; hence, the ad misericordiam fallacy is
effected by an ad populum argument.
The Ad Misericordiam as a Nonfallacious Argument
Non-fallacious occurrences of the ad misericordiam
include arguments where the appeal to pity or a related emotion is the subject
of the argument and is a pertinent or germane reason for acceptance of the
conclusion.
In the following examples, the appeal to emotions of pity or misery is
relevant to establishing the truth or falsity of the conclusion; consequently,
these ad misericordiam arguments are not fallacious:
Example 1: Elizabeth Gurley Flynn enumerates some of the reasons she became
a labor organizer:
“The conditions in the textile towns of New Hampshire and Massachusetts
[consisted of] huge gray mills, like prisons, barrack-like company boarding
houses, long hours, low wages, long periods of slack … I saw lard
instead of butter on neighbors' tables, children without underwear in cold New
England winters, a girl scalped by an unguarded machine in a mill across the
street from our school. I saw an old man weeping as they put him in the lockup
as a tramp.
[So] … I became a labor organizer. … I was determined to do
something about the bad conditions under which our family and all around us
suffered. I have
stuck to that purpose for 46 years.”
Comment: No fallacy occurs since her reasons provide relevant evidence for
dedicating her life to improving working conditions.
Example 2: Crito tries to convince Socrates to escape from prison:
“Nor can I think that you are at all justified, Socrates, in betraying
your own life when you might be saved … [Y]ou are deserting your own
children; for you might bring them up and educate them; instead of which you
go away and leave them, and they will have to take their chance; and if they
do not meet with the usual fate of orphans, there will be small thanks to you.
No man should bring children into the world who is unwilling to persevere to
the end in their nurture and education.”
Comment: Crito's appeal to pity or misery is not fallacious: Crito points out
the appalling, but relevant, effects of Socrates losing his life.
Example 3: During a 2017 News Conference President Trump states:
“[W]e are going to be working very hard on the inner cities, having to
do with education, having to do with crime. … You go to some of these
inner city places and it's so sad when you look at the crime. You have people
— and I've seen this, and I've sort of witnessed it — in fact,
in two cases I have actually witnessed it. They lock themselves into
apartments, petrified to even leave, in the middle of the day. They're living
in hell.”
Regardless of what opinion one has about President Trump's tenure in office, this
argument provides relevant reasons for working to improve the condition of inner
cites in the U.S. so no fallacy occurs in this passage.
postscript
“For … pity … and such passion of the soul, do not pertain to
that matter [modes of persuasion] but relate rather to the juror [or judge]. …
For one must not warp the juror by inducing … pity: this would be just as
if someone should make crooked the measuring stick he is about to use.”
Rhetoric I.i.1354a (trans. Bartlett)
Notes: Argumentum ad Misericordiam
Hyperlinks go to page cited
|
|