|
Problems in Philosophy
Nature of Philosophy
|
|
|
|
Cite Entry
October 3 2025
00:16 EDT
Cloud Chamber: Positron Trace
“The Positive Electron”
Photo by Carl D. Anderson, 1932
Wikipedia
|
Introduction to Philosophy
Characteristics of a Philosophical Problem
Abstract: Philosophy is the systematic inquiry
into the principles and presuppositions of any endeavor. Philosophy
is characterized and some philosophical problems are illustrated.
- Some general comments about the nature of philosophy can
be summarized from the previous tutorial.
- Etymologically, "philosophy" can be broken into the
following roots and examples.
- philo — meaning “fond of, affinity for;”
e.g., the name “Philip” means “lover of
horses,” and “philanthropy” being “love of
humanity.”
- sophia — wisdom; e.g., the name “Sophie”;
implying “being wise,” and “sophisticated”
indicating “knowledge of the world and its culture.”
- A preliminary definition of philosophy and some general characteristics
of its problems might be of help to get us started.
- Philosophy is the systematic inquiry into the principles
and presuppositions of any endeavor.
- Almost any area of interest has philosophical aspects. For
example, if you name a subject of interest and place the phrase
“philosophy of” in front of it, as in philosophy of
science, philosophy of art, or philosophy of music, you would
be referring to the essential aspects of that subject.
Or if you were to name a subject area and place the word
“philosophy” after it, as in political philosophy or
ethical philosophy, you would likely be indicating the basics or
fundamentals of those subjects.
- Recently, philosophy of sport, medical ethics,
and ethics of genetics have generated much interest.
- Some restaurants have printed on the back of the
customer's bill their philosophy of restaurant management.
- In general, philosophy questions often are a series of
"why-questions," whereas science is often said
to ask "how-questions."
- E.g., asking "Why did you come to class today?"
is the beginning of a series of why-questions which ultimately
lead to the answer of the principles or presuppositions by which
you lead your life.
I.e., Answer: "To pass the course."
Question: "Why do you want to pass the course?"
Answer: "To graduate from college."
Question: "Why do you want to graduate?"
Answer: "To get a good job."
Question: "Why do you want a good job?"
Answer: "To make lots of money."
Question: "Why do you want to make money?"
Answer: "To be happy."
Hence, such a person attends class today in order to seek to fulfill
the fundamental desire to increase the chances for a good life.
- Avrum Stroll and Richard H. Popkin, in their highly readable book,
Introduction
to Philosophy, isolate seven characteristics of a philosophical
problem. These characteristics serve as a good introduction to mark some
of the perplexing kinds of problems which can arise when we take a
philosophical approach to ordinary things.
Philosophical Thought-Experiments from Metaphysics and
Epistemology
Characteristics |
Typical Examples |
1. A reflection about the world and the things in it. |
If I take a book off my hand, what's left on my hand? If
I take away the air, then what's left? If I take away the
space? With the space gone, nothing is left. Does everything
exist in nothing? |
2. A conceptual rather than a practical activity. |
According to Newton's gravitation theory, as the ballerina
on a New York stage moves, my balance is imperceptibly
affected. Since the earth's circumference is about 25,000
miles, and the earth spins around once every 24 hours, as
I sit at my desk, I am in reality looping through space in
giant arcs at over 25,000 miles per hour. |
3. The use of reason and argumentation to establish a
point. |
Does a tree falling in a forest with no one around to
hear it, make a sound? To solve, we distinguish two senses
of "sound": (1) hearing—a phenomenological
perception and (2) vibration—a longitudinal wave
in matter. So if no one is there to hear, there is no sound of
type 1, but there is sound of type 2, as can be determined
by the prior leaving a recording device on the scene. |
4. An explanation of the puzzling features of things. |
Does a mirror reverse left and right? If I move my right
hand, the image's left hand moves. But why then doesn't the
mirror reverse up and down? Why aren't the feet in the mirror
image at the top of the mirror? Why doesn't it change the
situation if I lie down or I rotate the mirror 90 degrees? |
5. Digging beyond the obvious. |
What is a fact? In science, facts are collected. Is a book
a fact? Is it a big or is it a little fact? Is the book a smaller
fact than the size of the earth which is a larger fact? If the book is
brown, does that fact make it a brown fact? If facts don't have size,
shape, or color, then do they actually exist in the world? And, if not,
then how can they be found? |
6. The search for principles which underlie phenomena. |
For example, is a geranium one flower or is it a combination of many small
flowers bunched together? Or consider when I turn on a computer, is this
action one event or many events? If it's many events, how many events is
it? |
7. Theory building from these principles. |
Is nature discrete or continuous? E.g., Consider Zeno's paradoxes
of motion. If you are to leave the classroom today, isn't it true
that you will have to walk at least half-way to the door? And then
when you get half-way, you will have to at least walk another half?
How many “halves” are there? On this strategy, you could
never leave. |
- In practice, philosophy is an attitude, an approach, or even a calling
to answer, to ask, or to comment upon certain peculiar kinds of questions.
As we saw previously, the problems of philosophy are often
relegated to the main divisions of philosophy: Epistemology, Metaphysics, and
Axiology (Ethics and Æsthetics).
- Philosophy as an attitude suggests a curiosity arising from
puzzles such as the following:
- Under the assumption that time is a dimension just like any other,
the case of the problem of the surprise examination can arise:
Suppose students obtain the promise from their teacher that a surprise
quiz scheduled be given next week will not be given, if the students
demonstrate how they can know, in advance, the day the teacher will
give the exam. Thus, the students can argue as follows: Assuming the
class meets only on Monday, Wednesday, and Friday, the students know
the surprise exam cannot be given on Friday because everyone would
know Thursday night that the following day is the only period left in
which to give the exam. One would think that the teacher could give
the exam Wednesday, but since Friday has been eliminated as a possibility,
on Tuesday night, the students would know that the only period left
in the week would be Wednesday (since Friday has already been eliminated;
hence, the exam could not be given Wednesday either. Monday, then, is
the only possible period left to offer the exam. But, of course, the
teacher could not give the exam Monday because the students would expect
the exam that day. Consequently, the teacher cannot give a surprise
examination next week.
- In his Nobel
Prize Lecture, Richard Feynman explained that from the perspective
of quantum electrodynamics, if an electron is seen as going forward in
time, a positron is the same particle moving backwards in time. Is such time-
reversal really possible?
- Is a positron, or even the earlier tachyon, discussed above,
associated with backward causation a possible event? Consider this
paradoxical result. Suppose a "positron gun" or a "tachyon
gun" would fire a particle going backward in time—it could
"trigger" an off-switch to turn off the gun before it could
be fired.
- This example is, of course, a thought-experiment. As Feynman noted
in his
Lectures on Physics,
"Philosophers say a great deal about what is absolutely necessary
for science, and it is always, so far as one can see, rather naive, and
probably wrong.
- Philosophy seeks an approach in order to devise a methodology to answer
such puzzles. Very often, all that is needed is to invoke old maxim, “When
there is a difficulty, try to make a distinction.”
- E.g., for the problem of the sound of a tree falling in a
forest with no one around to hear, all we need do is distinguish two
different senses of ”sound.“
- If by “sound”; is meant a “phenomenological perception
by a subject,” then no sound (“hearing”) would occur.
If by “sound” is meant “a longitudinal wave in matter,”
then a sound is discoverable by an apparatus such as a tape recorder.
- And, finally, philosophy is a calling — if a person has had experiences of curiosity,
discovery, and invention at an early age, these experiences could leave
an imprint on mind and character to last a lifetime.
- Backward
Causation. Jan Fey's entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
examines several paradoxes based on the notion where an effect temporally, but
not causally, precedes its cause.
- Paradox. An extensive
reference list of paradoxes in Wikipedia is summarized by topic in mathematics, logic,
practice, philosophy, psychology, physics and economics with links to more
extensive discussion.
- Unexpected
Hanging Paradox. Eric W. Weisstein at the site Wolfram MathWorld
provides another version of the Surprise Examination Paradox with a
list of further references.
“Language is a labyrinth of paths. You approach from
one side and know your way about; you approach the same
place from another side and no longer know your way about.”
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations Trans. G. E. M.
Anscombe, 3rd. ed. (New York: The Macmillan Company), 1958),
82e.
Read the disclaimer concerning this page.
1997-2025 Licensed under GFDL
and Creative
Commons 3.0
The “Copyleft” copyright assures the user the freedom
to use,
copy, redistribute, make modifications with the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.
The “Creative Commons” copyright assures the user the
freedom
to copy, distribute, display, and modify on the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.
|