September 19 2025
00:00 EDT
William James
Photograph 1887
Houghton Library
Harvard University
pfMS AM 1092 (1185)
|
Introduction to Philosophical Inquiry
Philosophy Readings
Abstract: These short, edited philosophy readings from the history of
philosophy contain essential study questions for each reading as well as research questions
for paper topics.
Links to, and abstracts of, online philosophy readings are listed below by topic. The reading selections
include (1) a short introduction to the author and the work, (2) study questions outlining
the main ideas presented in the reading, (3) the reading selection itself, and (4) research
topics based upon major ideas presented.
Acknowledgments: Editorial assistance for these philosophy readings is
contributed by Erin Sells (es), William (Bill) Poston (wvp), James Grindeland, Jarad L. Pace,
Jennifer Lovvorn, and Joshua A. Watt.
Translations: Philosophy readings translated by Hélène Brown,
Samuel P. Moody, and Christine Dorsey for this series are gratefully
acknowledged. These works were specifically created for this series of
readings, and the translators have generously granted the use of their work
under the terms of the GFDL and
under the Creative Commons
License Version 3.0 or later (q.v. footer).
The Main Philosophical Topics of Readings:
- Introduction to Philosophical Inquiry
- Philosophy of Life
- Philosophy of Religion
- Philosophical Ethics
- Epistemology
- Æsthetics
- Introduction to Philosophical Inquiry.
- Preface to Reading for Philosophical Inquiry, Why Open
Source? (PDF)
Almost all classic major works in philosophy and literature are
accessible via online sources on the Internet. Fortunately, many
of the influential and abiding works in philosophy are in the
public domain; these readings provide a convenient way to produce
quality learning experiences for almost anyone seeking information
and help. Our present collection of edited readings is free,
subject to the legal notice following the title page. 8 pp.
- Part I of Reading for Philosophical Inquiry Personal
Uses of Philosophy 3 pp. (PDF)
This introduction to the readings on philosophy of life is a summary
of the first set of readings.
- The Nature of Learning: Recognition of Different Perspectives
(PDF)
The role of facts in understanding, theory dependence of facts, and
In the Laboratory with Agassiz, by Samuel Scudder. 22 pp.
Quiz (PDF)
(HTML)
- The Nature of Philosophical Inquiry
(PDF) The characterization of
philosophy, Alexander Calandra's "Barometer Story," an account of
many different solutions to one practical problem, and a summary
of the main divisions of philosophy make up this excerpt from
Reading for Philosophical Inquiry. 20 pp.
- Philosophy of Life
- Plato,
Just Do What's Right (PDF)
In the dialogue entitled The Apology, Plato recounts the
trial of Socrates. In the first part of The Apology Socrates'
philosophy of life becomes evident as he skillfully defends himself from
his accusers. In his quest for self-knowledge, Socrates spent many years
methodically questioning practically anyone who claimed to be knowledgeable
about something and, in so doing, managed to alienate influential persons.
The heart of his ethics is "the Socratic Paradox," a philosophy discussed in
the next chapter. Various interpretations of the Socratic ethics form the
foundation of most of the ethical theories in the Western World. (Plato,
The Apology Trans. Benjamin Jowlett.) 26 pp.
- Plato,
Seek Truth Rather Than Escape Death
(PDF) Plato continues
his account of the trial of Socrates. In this, the final part of
The Apology, Socrates is found guilty of the charges by a
vote of 281 to 220; undoubtedly, the ethical seriousness with which
Socrates spent his final days profoundly affected Plato as the young
student. Socrates now explains why he has nothing to fear from death.
Socrates argues that even if the soul were not immortal, death would
be a good. Nevertheless, Socrates did not doubt the immortality of
the soul.(Plato, The Apology. Trans. Benjamin Jowlett.) 13 pp.
- Bertrand Russell,
Enlargement of Self
(PDF) In this short reading
selection, Russell concludes his Problems of Philosophy, an early
work introducing philosophical inquiry. He thoughtfully summarizes
many uses of philosophy. The depth of the thinking evident here will
probably only be evident after careful re-reading. Philosophy is not
just another academic subject along side the others, instead
philosophy is the systematic inquiry into the presuppositions of any
field of study. Often philosophical wondering forms the historical
genesis of those disciplines. (From Bertrand Russell. Problems of
Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1912.) 13 pp.
- Leo Tolstoy,
Only Faith Can Give Truth
(PDF) >A Confession
from which the following selection is drawn, marks a significant
change from Tolstoy's earlier War and Peace and Anna Karenina.
These works, composed during his so-called first writing period,
established the Russian realistic novel as a major literary genre.
However, the mental crisis described below, from his later writings,
led to his own elucidation of the meaning of life. His writings from
this period have greatly influenced subsequent Utopians, pacifists,
and social activists. (From Lev Nikolayevich Tolstoy.
A Confession, 1882.) 19 pp.
- Albert Camus, Le Mythe de Sisyphe— trans.
Hélèn Brown (PDF)
Camus in Le Mythe de Sisyphe affirms that only by facing the
absurd can I act authentically; otherwise, I adopt a convenient
attitude of wishful thinking. Although I cannot count on the
consequences of my actions, my life's meaning comes from seizing
awareness of what I do. I must act in the face of meaningless—I
must revolt against the absurd—if I am not to despair from the ultimate
hopelessness and limitations of my life. (From Albert Camus.
Le Mythe de Sisyphe in Essais. Paris: Gallimard et
Calmann-Lévy., 1965. Part IV.) 11 pp.
- William James,
What Makes a Life Significant?
(PDF)
In his Talks to Students, James presents three lectures to
students — two of them, being The Gospel of Relaxation, and
On a Certain Blindness in Human Beings. The third talk is the one
presented here. His second, On a Certain Blindness in Human Beings,
has as its thesis that the worth of things depends upon the feelings we
have toward them. (From William James. Talks to Students.
1899.) 23 pp.
- Philosophy of Religion
- St. Anselm,
The Ontological Argument
(PDF) Although Anselm's argument
for God's existence presented in this article is based on predominately
on reason, Anselm presents the argument as clarification Christian
faith. The heart of his argument is the insight that if God is defined
as a “being than which no greater can be conceived,” then God
could not be conceived of as not existing because perfection, he thinks,
implies existence. Baruch Spinoza and René Descartes employed versions
of the ontological argument where the very concept of God as a perfect
being implies existence as a property. In philosophical jargon, a feature
of the essence of God is said to be existence. (Anselm,
Proslogium) 7 pp.
- Gaunilo,
An Answer to Anselm (PDF)
Gaunilo replies to Anselm's ontological argument in his Pro
Insipiente (a take-off of Anselm's reference to
the fool of Psalms) that the use of a concept does not imply that the
concept has an existent reference. He argues by analogy that many
ideas are only hypothetical. Note how in a later reading St. Thomas
Aquinas agrees with Gaunilo's analysis. Nathan Salmon has observed,
Philosophers who address the questions of what it is for an
individual to exist, or what it is for an individual to be actual,
often do so with reference to the fallacy they have uncovered in
the classical Ontological Argument for God's existence. Indeed,
the Ontological Argument is useful as a vehicle by which this
and other issues in ontology and the philosophy of logic may be
introduced and sharpened. (Nathan Salmon. Existence in
Philosophical Perspectives: Metaphysics, Volume 1. Edited by
James E. Tomberlin. Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing Co,
1987, 49.) (From Gaunilo. Pro Insipiente. In Behalf of the
Fool. 1078.) 6 pp.
- Immanuel Kant,
Existence Is Not a Predicate
(PDF) In Section IV. Of
the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of the Existence of God,
drawn from his Critique, Kant addresses the logical problem of
existential import. How do we talk or think about things without
supposing, in some sense at least, that they exist? Bertrand Russell
expressed one aspect of the problem this way: If it's false that the
present King of France is bald, then why doesn't this fact imply that
it's true the present King of France is not bald? When the existence
of the subjects of our statements are in question, the normal use of
logic becomes unreliable. Kant argues that the use of words (or
predicates ) alone does not necessarily imply the existence of
their referents. We can only assume the existence of entities named
by our words; we cannot prove existence by means of the use of
language alone. (From Immanuel Kant, The Critique of Pure
Reason. Trans. J. M. D. Meiklejohn. 1781. Bk.2 Ch. 3
§ IV, ¶ 55.) 10 pp.
- Thomas Aquinas,
From the Nature of the Universe
(PDF) Philosophical
reasoning, according to Thomas, is sufficient by itself, without faith
or revelation, to demonstrate that God exists. Thomas believes God's
existence, although not self-evident, can be made evident using reasoning
drawn from the nature and structure of the world. The so-called “five
ways” are taken from his Summa Theologica. Thomas, as
do many philosophers, believes that we can know by reason that God is,
but we cannot know what God is. In other words, the nature of God, often
defined by the characteristics of perfection, is, according to Thomas,
only a linguistic approximation. (From Thomas Aquinas, Summa
Theologica.) 9 pp.
- William Paley,
The Teleological Argument
(PDF) In his Natural Theology; or
Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity, Collected from the
Appearances of Nature, Paley argues for the existence
of God based upon the intricate design of the universe. On Paley's view,
just as the function and complexity of a watch implies a watch-maker
so likewise the function and complexity of the universe implies the
existence of a universe-maker. (From William Paley. Natural Theology.
Philadelphia: Parker, 1802.) 8 pp.
- David Hume,
Critique of the Design Argument
(PDF) Hume, in
his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion published
several years after his death, argued that God's existence can neither
be proved by á priori nor á posteriori means. Hume's
skepticism, however, left some room for empirical inquiry into the nature
of the world. Nevertheless, consider his famous conclusion in his
An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, If we take
in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance;
let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity
or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning, concerning
matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to flames: for it can
contain nothing but sophistry and illusion. (From David Hume.
Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. 1779.) 8 pp.
- Blaise Pascal,
The Wager (PDF)
Pascal's Pensées reveals a skepticism with respect
to natural theology. Pascal pointed out that the most important things
in life cannot be known with certainty; even so we must make choices.
His deep mysticism and religious commitment is reflective of Christian
existentialism, and Pascal's devotional writing is often compared to
Søren Kierkegaard's. The Pensées remained
fragmented devotional pieces until definitively edited and organized fifty
years ago. (Blaise Pascal. Pensées (1660). Trans. W. F. Trotter.
New York: Collier & Son, 1910.) 8 pp.
- Fyodor Dostoevsky,
The Problem of Evil
(PDF) In the The Brothers
Karamazov, Dostoevsky reveals deep psychological insight into the
nature of human morality. In this, his greatest work, he expresses the
destructive aspects of human freedom which can only be bound by God. In
Chapter 4 of that work, the death of an innocent child is seen to be an
inescapable objection to God's goodness. In this chapter Alyosha is the
religious foil to Ivan, his intellectual older brother. (Fyodor Dostoevsky.
“Rebellion” in the The Brothers Karamazov (1879).
Trans. by Constance Garnett.) 15 pp.
- Philosophical Ethics
- Free Will and Determinism PDF
forthcoming. In the meantime, some of the major philosophical and theological
doctrines concerning freewill and determinism are outlined on this page:
Free Will and Determinism: Some Varieties.
- Hubbard Winslow,
Conscience Determines What is Right
(PDF) (HTML)
In his Moral Philosophy, Winslow argues that basing ethics
on theoretical philosophy is a prevailing error. Metaphysics and
logic, he argues, are not subservient to everyday consciousness of freedom
and responsibility. In this reading, Winslow argues that philosophy should
be used in the service of faith. He believes faith is a direct
manifestation of the truth presented to each person's conscience and
adduces just as [w]e must not wait until we can philosophize upon food
before we eat… so also [n]either should we wait to learn all
the grounds and reasons of duty, before doing what we already know to be
right. (From Moral Philosophy; Analytical, Synthetical, and
Practical (New York: D. Appleton and Company), 1856.) 12 pp.
- Alexander Bain,
Conscience is Learned
(PDF) (HTML)
In his Moral Science, Bain uses his insight into the nature
of the will for an explication of ethical theory. In many ways, Bain
anticipated pragmatism; in fact, Charles Sanders Pierce's well-known
statement, different beliefs are distinguished by the different modes
of action to which they give rise originated from Bain's notion of
belief as the preparation to act. In this reading, Bain explains the origin
of conscience and how our consciences are shaped. If Bain is correct,
conscience cannot be a reliable guide to a consistent ethics across different
cultures and during different times. (From Alexander Bain, Moral Science:
A Compendium of Ethics (New York: D. Appleton, 1869).) 12 pp.
- Richard Price,
How Do We Know What's Right?
(PDF) (HTML)
Richard Price argues that moral principles, just like the principles of
geometry, are universally, necessarily, and eternally true. He believes
ideas of right and wrong originate in the understanding; indeed, Price
anticipates not only Kant's recognition of the origin of ideas of judgment
and comparison — whereby reason discriminates among moral ideas, and
reason alone is a sufficient basis for action, but also W. D. Ross's
deontological ethics or rational intuitionism — whereby morality
is objective, and this objectivity is evaluative knowledge not empirically
confirmable.
Price concludes ideas of right and wrong are simple ideas intuitively
discriminated by the understanding since they cannot be defined more
simply or even defined in different terms. For him, right
and wrong are objective properties of actions, and as characteristics
of actions, right and wrong are not subjectively dependent upon
sensations arising from the nature of our minds. Just as rightness and
wrongness are characteristics of behavior, so also mass and solidity
are characteristics of natural objects. In both cases, these kinds of
facts are not known through observation but rather by means of reason
as one aspect of the faculty of human understanding. Through introspection,
Price concludes the source of the moral ideas of right and wrong is an
intuition of the nature of things. In this manner, we can objectively
perceive what is right and wrong in the world. Hence, Price rejects ethical
naturalism, the view that ethical terms are ultimately definable in the
empirical terms of the natural sciences. In this, he anticipates G. E.
Moore's discussion of the naturalistic fallacy in Principia Ethica
that ethical concepts must be defined in terms of nonnatural properties.
Finally, Price opposes the divine command theory that actions are
right only for the reason of God's commanding them. Price argues if
the divine command theory were true, then we would have to conclude
there would be no reason for God to command what He does. (From
Review of the Principal Questions of Morals, 3rd. ed. (London:
T. Cadell in the Strand, 1787), 8-79 passim.) 21 pp.
- F. H. Bradley,
Why Should I Be Moral?
(PDF) (HTML)
In his essay, Bradley states the aim of ethics is the realization of
self: willing and acting in accordance with an ideal toward a moral end.
He recognizes the realization of an ideal self is necessarily conditioned
by an unrealized self, and in this regard, his ethics does not provide
a metaphysical basis for relating the thought of the ideal with the reality
of the actual. The metaphysical scaffolding for this he attempts to achieve
in his later works, Principles of Logic and Appearance
and Reality. The first part of our reading raises the question why
I should be moral, but Bradley concludes the why-question is inaptly phrased.
Instead, he thinks the question should be asked along the lines of what I
am to do or be. What is the ideal I seek to realize? (From F. H. Bradley,
Ethical Studies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1876), 58-84
passim.) 17 pp.
Quiz(PDF)
(HTML)
- Charles A. Ellwood,
Morality as an Evolutionary Result
(PDF) (HTML)
In his Sociology and Modern Social Problems, Charles A. Ellwood,
outlines the origin of moral codes and ethics in terms of the competition
and conflict inherent in the evolution and development of sociological
groups. He maintains that morality is a consequence of survival, and,
in light of these studies, the study of morality can now be considered
an essential part of sociology. The consequences of this reading would
seem to imply that ethics is culturally relative to the specific times
and conditions of disparate societies — a sociological view expounded
also by Edward Westermarck, William Graham Sumner, and Ruth Benedict.
In the short reading selection below, Ellwood explains why Morality…
is not anything arbitrarily designed by the group, but is a standard of
conduct which necessities of social survival require. (From Charles A.
Ellwood, Sociology and Modern Social Problems (New York: American
Book Company, 1910), 20-12; 42-50.) 16 pp.
- Edward Westermarck,
Ethics Are Relative
(PDF) (HTML)
In his Ethical Relativity, Edward Westermarck argues for both
psychological and ethical relativism and attempts to base ethics on the
biological basis of emotion. Westermarck holds that impartial moral emotions
or moral sentiments are the basis for customary moral judgments. Consequently,
Westermarck concludes moral values cannot be objective since they originate
in emotion. Even so, impartial or dispassionate moral emotion is not entirely
subjective since it is an customary human reaction to a particular moral
experience. In the book from which our reading selection is taken, Westermarck
argues forcefully for ethical relativism by emphasizing that there is no
empirical basis for objective standards in ethical theory. Nevertheless, even
though ethical judgments are based on feelings, he does not believe ethical
relativism leads to ethical subjectivism. (From Edward Westermarck,
Ethical Relativity (New York: Littlefield, Adams & Company,
1932).) 16 pp.
- Baruch Spinoza,
Human Beings are Determined
(PDF) Sometime after his sentence of
excommunication Spinoza began working of the ideas which would eventually be
published as The Ethics, a book published posthumously from
the fear of persecution from the charge of the blasphemy of pantheism.
Pantheism should be distinguished from panentheism which is the view
that gods are in all things. Spinoza believed, much as Socrates believed,
the excellent life is the life of reason in the service of one's own being.
The soul seeks knowledge as a good; indeed, the soul's highest good is
knowledge of God. Spinoza argues that the mind and the body are, in reality,
only one thing but can be thought of in two different ways. The person who
understands how the soul is part of the system of nature also understands,
at the same time, how the soul is part of God. In sum, Spinoza's monism
is the deductive exposition of existence as the complete unity of God and
nature. According to this view, human beings have no free will, and the
world cannot be evil. (From Baruch Spinoza. The Ethics: Demonstrated in
Geometric Order. Translated by R.H.M. Elwes. 1883. Part III: On the
Origin and the Nature of the Emotions — Note to Proposition 2.) 10 pp.
- William James,
The Will to Believe (PDF)
In his Will to Believe and Other Essays, James argues that it is
not unreasonable to believe hypotheses that cannot be known or established to
be true by scientific investigation. When some hypotheses of ultimate concern
arise, he argues that our faith can pragmatically shape future outcomes. Much
as in Pascal's Wager, by not choosing, he thinks, we lose possibility for
meaningful encounters. (From William James. The Will to Believe and Other
Essays. London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1897.) 14 pp.
- Plato,
The Ring of Gyges (PDF)
Glaucon, the main speaker of this reading from Plato's Republic,
expresses a widely and deeply-held ethical point of view known as ethical egoism
a view taught by a Antiphon, a sophistic contemporary of Socrates. Egoistic
theories are founded on the belief that everyone acts only from the motive of
self-interest. For example, the egoist accounts for the fact that people help
people on the basis of what the helpers might get in return from those helped
or others like them. This view, neither representative of Plato's nor of
Socrates's philosophy, is presented here by Glaucon as a stalking horse
for the development of a more thoroughly developed ethical theory. Although
Socrates held that everyone attempts to act from the motive of
self-interest, his interpretation of that motive is quite
different from the view elaborated by Glaucon because Glaucon seems
unaware of the attendant formative effects on the soul by actions for
short-term pleasure. (From Plato. The Republic. Trans. by Benjamin
Jowlett, Book II, 358d—361d.) 9 pp.
- Aristotle,
Life of Excellence: Living and Doing Well
(PDF) In the Nicomachean Ethics,
Aristotle argues that what we seek is eudaimonia, a term
translated in this reading as happiness. Eudaimonia
is better expressed as well-being or excellence of performing
the proper function. When Aristotle explains human virtue, he is not
discussing what we now refer to as (Victorian) virtue. He is clarifying
the peculiar excellence of human beings in the same manner as we often
speak of the peculiar excellence attributable to the nature of a thing.
For example, a tool is useful in virtue of the fact that it performs its
function well. Aristotle's purpose in the Nicomachean Ethics is not just
to explain the philosophy of the excellence for human beings but also to
demonstrate specifically how human beings can lead lives of excellence as
activity in accordance with practical and theoretical reason. (From
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics.) 18 pp.
- Jeremy Bentham,
Happiness is the Greatest Good, (PDF) In his Introduction to
the Principles of Morals and Legislation, Bentham attributes the
inconsistency of English law, its complexity as well as it inhumanness,
to its foundation on the moral feelings of sympathy and antipathy.
He argues that the laws of all nations should be rationally based, not
emotionally based, on what appeared to him to be the self-evident principle
of the greatest good for the greatest number. In an effort to apply this
principle of utility to legal reform, Bentham develops the hedonistic, or
as it is sometimes called, the felicific calculus. As an ethical teleologist,
Bentham devises a method of calculating the most pleasure vis-á-vis
the least pain by means of a quantitative scale. Historically, the hedonistic
calculus was a major step in the development of rational decision theory and
utility theory. (From Jeremy Bentham. Introduction to the Principles
of Morals and Legislation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1907.)
15 pp.
- John Stuart Mill,
Utilitarianism (PDF)
Much as his father and Jeremy Bentham assumed, Mill also believes an action
is right if and only if the action produces on balance more good than bad
than any other action available to the person. Also, as well, with them,
he identifies pleasure or happiness as the only intrinsic good. Mill explicates
and broadens this view in his Utilitarianism where he avoids the
limited hedonism of Bentham and the egoism of his father by noting first that
pleasures of the mind are preferable to those of the body and second that
helping others is one of the ways to maximize an individual's good. In general,
Mill's ethics turns out to be positivistic and empirical: moral rules are
justified in experience by their usefulness for human welfare. In particular,
the moral rules of common sense, such as speaking truthfully, are gleaned from
the recognition of their utility as founded on historical knowledge and
experience. Although Mill's utilitarianism is roundly criticized by the British
idealists T. H. Green and F. H. Bradley, his ethics stands as perhaps the most
influential philosophy of individual and social liberty in the nineteenth
century. (From John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism (London: Parker,
Son, and Bourn, West Strand: 1863), 9-29; 51-60.) 27 pp.
- G. E. Moore,
The Objectivity of Moral Judgments
(PDF) forthcoming.
- Friedrich Nietzsche,
Slave and Master Morality
(PDF)
In Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche detects two types of morality
mixed not only in higher civilization but also in the psychology of the
individual. Master-morality values power, nobility, and independence: it
stands beyond good and evil. Slave-morality values sympathy,
kindness, and humility and is regarded by Nietzsche as herd-morality.
The history of society, Nietzsche believes, is the conflict between
these two outlooks: the herd attempts to impose its values universally
but the noble master transcends their mediocrity. (From Friedrich
Nietzsche. Beyond Good and Evil. Trans. by Helen Zimmern
(1909-1913), 257-261.) 12 pp.
- T. H. Huxley,
Evolution and Ethics
(PDF) (HTML)
In his Romanes Lecture entitled Evolution and Ethics, T. H. Huxley,
argues that the moral progress of civilization is not a product of
the evolution of the natural world. The phrase survival of the fittest
simply means the adaptation to current conditions, with no implication
whatsoever of moral improvement. In point of fact, civil law, customs, and
morals sustain those who are ethically best; moreover, science and the arts
have been instrumental in opposing the natural condition of competition for
survival. Huxley reasons that only man's intelligence can effect modification
of the conditions of existence and perhaps, as well, change
mankind itself in order to stave off the natural circumstances of existence.
(From T. H. Huxley, Collected Essays (London: Macmillan, 1893-4),
Vol. 9, 46-116.) 13 pp.
- José Ortega y Gasset,
Man, as Project —trans. Samuel P.
Moody (PDF)
(HTML) Ortega seeks to answer the question,
Qué es la técnica? Human beings, unlike other living
things, are not limited by natural circumstance because they can, so to speak,
reform nature through technical invention and accomplishment. The essence
of being human is this adaptation of an environment to the individual—
not the adaptation of the individual to the environment. The attainment of
such practical technicality is not based on the instinct to live so much as
it is based on the necessity to live well, even though these extra-natural
ideals of well-being develop in different ways in different historical
periods. Since man's being diverges from his nature, to live authentically,
Ortega writes, each person must uniquely construct his life's aspirations
through historical reason. An authentic life is one where a person
becomes his mission in life; an inauthentic (and consequently immoral)
life is a life where a person avoids his vital project by taking refuge
in happenstance. (From José Ortega Y Gasset. “Meditación
de la técna,” in Ensimismamiento y alteractión. Buenos
Aires: Espasa-Calpe, 1939.) 20 pp.
- J. P. Sartre,
Man Makes Himself (PDF)
In his Existentialism Is A Humanism, a public lecture given in
1946, Sartre provides one of the clearest and most striking insights into the
anti-philosophy termed existentialism. Many of the issues discussed here
are part of the family-relation of concepts often cited as being part of the
existential movement. By its very nature existentialism cannot be consistently
thought of as a popular philosophy both because of its rejection of crowd values
as well as its rejection of a common human nature. Indeed, Jaspers, Heidegger,
and Camus all disassociated themselves from existentialism after the enormous
success of Sartre's works. Even Sartre himself later turned away from the unique
individuality of existential perspective to a anomalous political Marxism. (From
Jean-Paul Sartre. Existentialism Is A Humanism. Trans. by Philip
Mairet. Public Lecture, 1946.) 25 pp.
- Epistemology
- August Comte,
Positive Philosophy (PDF)
In his Cours de Philosophie Positive, Comte explains how societies
evolve in accordance with natural law. The three stages discussed here, the
theological-military, the metaphysical-transitional, and the scientific-industrial,
he argues, progress according to a law of social development. Furthermore, he
advocates a historical method of study for social science based on empirical methods.
(From August Comte. Cours de Philosophie Positive. Trans. Paul Descours and H. G.
Jones, 1905.) 6 pp.
- Frederick Engels,
Science of Natural Processes
(PDF) In this reading from the second
publication of Ludwig Feuerbach and the Outcome of Classical German
Philosophy, Frederick Engels argues that three recent discoveries in the
sciences provide the basis by which all aspects of the universe can be understood
in terms of the philosophy of materialism. Wöhler's synthesis of urea proves
that organic processes are explainable in terms of inorganic processes. The theory
of the cell discovered by Schwann and Schleiden proves that the physiological
basis of all living things is the same, and Darwin's theory of evolution indicates
no difference in kind between human and all other forms of life. Finally, the
discovery of the mechanical equivalent of heat (that heat is just matter in motion),
proved that subjective properties (heretofore considered mental qualities) are
equivalent to material processes. On Engels' proposal, soul, spirit, and ideas are
part of the material processes of nature. One arguable consequence of the unification
of science provided by the theory of mechanistic materialism is the impossibility of
the discipline of an ethics based on choice. How could free will be possible in a
deterministic and materialistic world? (Frederick Engels. Ludwig Feuerbach and
the Outcome of Classical German Philosophy. 1888.) 11 pp.
- John Stuart Mill,
A Science of Human Nature
(PDF) In our selection from A
System of Logic,his first significant book, Mill argues that a science of
human nature is no different from any other kind of exact science. In astronomy,
the movement of the planets can be predicted with certainty because the laws of
motions and the antecedent circumstances can be, he thinks, known with certainty.
The rise and fall of the tides, on the other hand, can only be imprecisely known
because local antecedent conditions cannot be known or measured exactly. The study
of human nature is similar to tidology because of the complexity of the factors
in human action. Nevertheless, Mill argues that, in principle, both tidology and
human nature can become exact sciences. (From John Stuart Mill. A System
of Logic: Ratiocinative and Inductive. New York: Longmans, Green, and
Co., 1893, Bk. VI, Ch. IV.) 9 pp.
- Harold H. Joachim,
Coherence Theory of Truth
(PDF) In his The Nature of Truth; An
Essay, Harold H. Joachim gives one of the classic statements of the coherence
theory of truth. On his view, human truth is incomplete, for there can be no absolute
truth unless the whole system of knowledge could be completed. Whatever is true not
only is consistent with a system of other propositions but also is true to the extent
that it is a necessary constituent of a systematic whole. Joachim emphasizes that
since the truth is a property of the whole, individual propositions are only true
in a derivative sense—literally they are partly true and partly false. Only
the system of an extensive body of propositions as a whole can be rightly said to be
true. (From Harold H. Joachim. The Nature of Truth; An Essay. Oxford:
Clarendon Press. 1906.) 15 pp.
- William James,
Pragmatic Theory of Truth (PDF) In his Pragmatism,
William James characterizes truth in terms of usefulness and acceptance.
In general, on his view, truth is found by attending to the practical
consequences of ideas. To say that truth is mere agreement of ideas with
matters of fact, according to James, is incomplete, and to say that truth
is captured by coherence is not to distinguish it from a consistent falsity.
In a genuine sense, James believes we construct truth in the process of
successful living in the world: truth is in no sense absolute. Beliefs
are considered to be true if and only if they are useful and can be
practically applied. At one point in his works, James states, …the
ultimate test for us of what a truth means is the conduct it dictates or
inspires. Certainly, one difficulty in understanding James lies
in the interpretation of his rhetorical flourishes. (From William James.
Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. New York:
Longman Green and Co., 1907.) 15 pp.
- Bertrand Russell,
What is Truth? (PDF)
In the chapter Truth and Falsehood in his Problems of Philosophy,
Russell advances the correspondence theory of truth. On this theory, truth
is understood in terms of the way reality is described by our beliefs. A belief
is false when it does not reflect states-of-affairs, events, or things accurately.
In order for our beliefs to be true, our beliefs must agree with what is real. Note
that the correspondence theory is not concerned with the discovery of truth or a
means for obtaining true belief because the theory, itself, cannot establish the
nature of reality. (Bertrand Russell. The Problems of Philosophy. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1912.) 13 pp.
- Aristotle,
The Sea-Fight Tomorrow (PDF)
In his On Interpretation, Aristotle outlines the basis for what has
been designated since the Middle Ages the “Square of Opposition” under
the assumption that statements have existential import. Statements involving future
possibilities pose unique problems for logic, and there have been many attempts to
develop a consistent and reasonably complete temporal logic. In this reading selection,
Aristotle concludes that sentences about the future do not quality as being statements
at all since, strictly speaking they have no truth value — hence, the all-important
law of the excluded middle is not in question. On this view, sentences concerning
future contingencies involve possibility. Yet, there is more to the story when
the question of future truths is related to the metaphysical presuppositions
when actuality and potentiality used in a logic system. (From Aristotle.
On Interpretation. Trans. E. M. Edghill, 350 BCE, Part 9.) 9 pp.
- Æsthetics
- Joseph Adddison,
Pleasures of the Imagination
(PDF) In his and Richard Steele's The
Spectator, Addison developed an essay style which greatly influenced the
writings in eighteenth-century periodicals. In the short well-known passages in
our readings on the pleasures of the imagination, Addison clearly notes some
first suggestions towards a theory of æsthetics. His contribution represents a
shift in emphasis from the creations of the artist to the pleasures of the connoisseur;
for this reason, Addison's essays had great appeal to the rising middle class seeking
to improve their refinement and taste. Addison notes that of the pleasures of sense,
the understanding and the imagination, only the latter pleasures originate from sight.
Whether or not imaginative pleasures derive from the appearance or the ideas of visible
objects, the pleasure, he thinks, is due to their expansiveness, novelty, or beauty.
He argues that the purpose of such pleasure is attributable to the Supreme Being
providing light and color to behold His works. Accordingly, Addison believes beauty
in nature surpasses that of art, even though different aspects of beauty in each form
enhance the beauty of the other. (From Joseph Addison, The Spectator.
London: George Routledge and Sons, Ltd. 1891. Letters No. 411 Saturday, June 21, 1712;
No. 412 Monday, June 23, 1712; No. 413 Tuesday, June 24, 1712; and No. 414 Wednesday,
June 25, 1712.) 19 pp.
- Clive Bell,
Art. (PDF)
(HTML) Bell outlines a formalist theory based
on his definition of art as significant form. True art, he believes,
exhibits combinations of lines and colors which engender intellectual
recognition and æsthetic experience in persons of taste. The resultant
æsthetic emotion, he believes, is unique, morally transcendent,
and independent of other kinds of human emotion. Æsthetic value
in art, he argues, is based solely on the forms and relations which
evoke an ecstatic artistic response. Since æsthetic response to
significant form in art is a basic and distinct emotion, forms and relations
in art are intuited as a pure, simple quality intuitively known by individuals
with the rare gift of artistic appreciation. Significant form, itself,
is a quality of the artistic work and not of the resultant emotion or
perception, even though the form initiates æsthetic experience. (From
Clive Bell, Art. London: Chatto & Windus. 1914.) 24 pp.
Quiz (PDF)
(HTML)
If you have questions or suggestions about the readings, email
philhelp@gmail.com. All readings are freely available
in accordance with the GFDL or Creative
Commons 3.0 or above license.

A philosophical problem has the form, I don't know my way about. Ludwig
Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations 3rd. ed., trans. G. E. M. Anscombe
(New York: Macmillan, 1958), ¶ 123.
Relay corrections or suggestions to philhelp@gmail
Read the disclaimer concerning this page.
1997-2025 Licensed under GFDL
and Creative
Commons 3.0
The “Copyleft” copyright assures the user the freedom
to use,
copy, redistribute, make modifications with the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.
The “Creative Commons” copyright assures the user the
freedom
to copy, distribute, display, and modify on the same terms.
Works for sale must link to a free copy.
|